Mr. Wise is a
noted white anti-racist activist. The following is a December 23, 2005 essay,
followed by a December 29 review by Mr. Wise of comments generated
by the original piece. Both can be found at www.timwise.org.
As has been the case every year for as long as I can
recall, an American college campus is once again embroiled in controversy
over the expression of racism in its hallowed halls, and what it
may seek to do in response.
This time the place is Bellarmine University, a Catholic
college in Louisville, Kentucky, where, for the past several months,
freshman Andrei Chira has been sporting an armband for "Blood
and Honour" - a British-based neo-Nazi and skinhead-affiliated
musical movement, that calls for "white pride" and white
power. Created originally as a magazine by Ian Stuart of the Hitler-friendly
and openly fascist band, Skrewdriver, the Blood and Honour "movement"
promotes bands that sing about racial cleansing and the deportation,
if not extermination, of blacks and Jews. Blood and Honour's symbol,
similar to the Nazi swastika, is that of the South African white
supremacist movement, and is featured prominently on Chira's armband.
Chira, for his part, seems more confused than dangerous.
All in the same breath he insists he is not a Nazi or neo-Nazi,
but that he is a National Socialist (the term for which Nazi
is shorthand). He insists he is not a white supremacist, a racist,
or anti-Jewish, yet claims to be a supporter of the American National
Socialist Movement (NSM), which calls for citizenship to be limited
to those who are non-Jewish, heterosexual whites, and which group
praises Hitler on its website.
All of which raises the larger question, which is
not so much whether or not Chira should have the freedom to be an
ignorant lout, but rather, how did someone so incapable of evincing
even a modicum of intelligible (or merely internally consistent)
thought, get admitted to a good college like Bellarmine in the first
place? Are there no standards anymore?
Naturally, the debate has now begun to turn on the
issue of free speech: Does the University have the right to sanction
Chira or force him to remove the armband, or do his First Amendment
rights trump concerns about the feelings of students of color, Jews
(yes there are some at the Catholic school, both students and professors),
and others who are made to feel unsafe by a neo-Nazi symbol?
It's a tug-of-war that has divided American higher
education for years, with some schools passing restrictive codes
limiting language or symbols that express open racial or religious
hostility, and others taking a more hands-off approach. Bellarmine
has remained uncommitted to any particular course of action. The
University President has spoken in defense of Chira's free speech
rights (and of the principle, more broadly), and has called for
a committee to study the issue and determine what kind of policy
the school should adopt to deal with hate speech.
Buzz around campus has been split between free speech
absolutists on the one hand (who seem to predominate), and those
concerned about the way in which racist symbols might intimidate
and further marginalize already isolated students, faculty and staff
of color, on the other. Faculty have sniped at one another from
both sides of the issue, as have students, and a group of about
a dozen students recently launched a sit-in outside the office of
the Vice-President for Student Affairs, to insist on the inviolability
of free speech rights.
As students prepare to return for the spring semester,
there is little doubt but that the issue will dominate time and
energy on the Bellarmine campus in months to come, and that how
the school resolves the issue will come to inform other colleges
with regard to their own hate speech policies. Having spoken recently
at Bellarmine, and having met dozens of conscientious students and
faculty there, concerned about addressing racism, I would like to
take this opportunity to chime in, both regarding the existing free
speech debate, and the larger (and I think more important) issue,
which is how best to respond to racism, whether at a college or
in society more broadly.
To be honest, I have never found the main arguments
of either the free speech absolutists or those who support hate
speech restrictions to be particularly persuasive.
On the one hand, the free speech folks ignore several
examples of speech limitations that we live with everyday, and that
most all would think legitimate. So, we are not free to slander
others, to print libelous information about others, to engage in
false advertising, to harass others, to print and disseminate personal
information about others (such as their confidential medical or
financial records), to engage in speech that seeks to further a
criminal conspiracy, to speak in a way that creates a hostile work
environment (as with sexual harassment), to engage in plagiarized
speech, or to lie under oath by way of dishonest speech. In other
words, First Amendment absolutism is not only inconsistent with
Constitutional jurisprudence; it is also a moral and practical absurdity,
as these and other legitimate limitations make fairly apparent.
Secondly, the free speech rights of racists, by definition,
must be balanced against the equal protection rights of those targeted
by said speech. If people have the right to be educated or employed
in non-hostile environments (and the courts and common sense both
suggest they do), and if these rights extend to both public and
private institutions (and they do), then to favor the free speech
rights of racists, over and above the right to equal protection
for their targets, is to trample the latter for the sake of the
former. In other words, there is always a balance that must be struck,
and an argument can be made that certain kinds of racist speech
create such a hostile and intimidating environment that certain
limits would be not only acceptable, but required, as a prerequisite
for equal protection of the laws, and equal opportunity.
So, for example, face-to-face racist invective could
be restricted, as could racist speech that carried with it the implied
threat of violence. Whether or not a neo-Nazi symbol of a movement
that celebrates Adolph Hitler qualifies in that regard, is the issue
to be resolved; but certainly it should not be seen as obvious that
any and all speech is protected, just because of the right to free
speech in the abstract.
Not to mention, does anyone honestly believe that
Bellarmine, a Catholic school, would allow (or that most of the
free speech absolutists would insist that they should allow)
students to attend class with t-shirts that read: "Hey Pope
Benedict: Kiss my pro-choice Catholic ass!" or "My priest
molested me and all I got from my diocese was this lousy t-shirt?"
No doubt such garments would be seen as disruptive, and precisely
because they do not truly express a viewpoint or any substantive
content, but rather, simply toss rhetorical grenades for the sake
of shock value (likely part of Chira's motivation too).
Chira's armband, in that regard, is quite different
from a research paper, dissertation, or even a speech given on a
soapbox, or article written for his own newspaper, if he had one:
namely, unlike these things, the armband is not a rebuttable argument,
nor does it put forth a cogent position to which "more speech"
can be the obvious solution. It provokes an emotional response only,
and little else.
At the same time, the arguments of those who would
move to ban hate speech have also typically fallen short of the
mark, at least in my estimation.
To begin with, speech codes have always seemed the
easy way out: the least costly, most self-righteous, but ultimately
least effective way to address racism. First, such codes only target,
by necessity, the most blatant forms of racism - the overtly hateful,
bigoted and hostile forms of speech embodied in slurs or perhaps
neo-Nazi symbolism - while leaving in place,
also by necessity, the legality of more nuanced, high-minded, and
ultimately more dangerous forms of racism. So racist books like
The Bell Curve, which argues that blacks are genetically
inferior to whites and Asians, obviously would not be banned under
hate speech codes (nor should they be), but those racists who were
too stupid to couch their biases in big words and footnotes would
be singled out for attention: in which case, we'd be punishing not
racism, per se, or even racist speech, but merely the inarticulate
expression of the same.
In turn, this kind of policy would then create a false
sense of security, as institutions came to believe they had really
done something important, even as slicker forms of racism remained
popular and unaddressed. Furthermore, such policies would also reinforce
the false and dangerous notion that racism is limited to the blatant
forms being circumscribed by statute, or that racists are all obvious
and open advocates of fascism, rather than the oftentimes professional,
respectable, and destructive leaders of our institutions: politicians,
cops, and bosses, among others.
Secondly, hate speech codes reinforce the common tendency
to view racism on the purely individual level - as a personality
problem in need of adjustment, or at least censure - as opposed
to an institutional arrangement, whereby colleges, workplaces and
society at large manifest racial inequity of treatment and opportunity,
often without any bigotry whatsoever.
So, for example, racial inequity in the job market
is perpetuated not only, or even mostly by overt racism - though
that too is still far too common - but rather by way of the "old
boy's networks," whereby mostly white, middle class and above,
and male networks of friends, neighbors and associates pass along
information about job openings to one another. And this they do,
not because they seek to deliberately keep others out, but simply
because those are the people they know, live around, and consider
their friends. The result, of course, is that people of color and
women of all colors remain locked out of full opportunity.
Likewise, students seeking to get into college are
given standardized tests (bearing little relationship to academic
ability), which are then used to determine in large measure where
(or even if) they will go to college at all; this, despite
the fact that these students have received profoundly unstandardized
educations, have been exposed to unstandardized resources, unstandardized
curricula, and have come from unstandardized and dramatically unequal
backgrounds. As such, lower income students and students of color
- who disproportionately come out on the short end of the resource
stick - are prevented from obtaining true educational equity with
their white and more affluent peers. And again, this would have
nothing to do with overt bias, let alone the presence of neo-Nazis
at the Educational Testing Service or in the admissions offices
of any given school.
In other words, by focusing on the overt and obvious
forms of racism, hate speech codes distract us from the structural
and institutional changes necessary to truly address racism and
white supremacy as larger social phenomena. And while we could,
in theory, both limit racist speech and respond to institutional
racism, doing the former almost by definition takes so much energy
(if for no other reason than the time it takes to defend the effort
from Constitutional challenges), that getting around to the latter
never seems to follow in practice. Not to mention, by passing hate
speech codes, the dialogue about racism inevitably (as at Bellarmine)
gets transformed into a discussion about free speech and censorship,
thereby fundamentally altering the focus of our attentions, and
making it all the less likely that our emphasis will be shifted
back to the harder and more thoroughgoing work of addressing structural
racial inequity.
Perhaps most importantly, even to the extent we seek
to focus on the overt manifestations of racism, putting our emphasis
on ways to limit speech implies that there aren't other ways to
respond to overt bias that might be more effective and more creative,
and engage members of the institution in a more thoroughgoing and
important discussion about individual responsibilities to challenge
bigotry.
So instead of banning racist armbands, how much better
might it be to see hundreds of Bellarmine students donning their
own come spring: armbands saying things like: "Fuck Nazism,"
"Fuck Racism," or, for that matter, "Fuck You, Andrei"
(hey, free speech is free speech, after all).
That a lot of folks would be more offended by the
word “fuck,” both in this article and on an armband, than by the
political message of Chira's wardrobe accessory, of course, says
a lot about what's wrong in this culture, but that's a different
column for a different day. The point here is that such messages
would be a good way to test how committed people at Bellarmine really
are to free speech, and would also send a strong message that racism
will be met and challenged en masse, and not just via anonymous
e-mails.
In other words, if Chira is free to make people of
color uncomfortable, then others are sure as shit free to do the
same to him and others like him. Otherwise, freedom of speech becomes
solely a shield for members of majority groups to hide behind, every
time they seek to bash others.
Instead of banning hate speech, how much better might
it be if everyone at Bellarmine who insists that they don't agree
with Chira, but only support his rights to free speech, isolated
and ostracized him: refusing to speak to him, refusing to sit near
him, refusing to associate with him in any way, shape or form. That
too would be exercising free speech after all, since free speech
also means the freedom not to speak, in this case, to a jackass
like Andrei Chira.
Instead of banning hate speech, how much better might
it be for Bellarmine University to institutionalize practices and
policies intended to screen out fascist bottom-feeders like Chira
in the first place? After all, Bellarmine, like any college can
establish any number of requirements for students seeking to gain
admission, or staff seeking to work at the school, or faculty desiring
a teaching gig. In addition to scholarly credentials, why not require
applicants - whether for student slots or jobs - to explain how
they intend to further the cause of racial diversity and equity
at Bellarmine?
And before I'm accused of advocating the larding up
of the school's mission with politically correct platitudes, perhaps
it would be worth noting that these values are already part of Bellarmine's
Mission and Vision statements to begin with. To wit, the school's
Mission statement, which reads:
"Bellarmine University is an independent,
Catholic university in the public interest, serving the region,
the nation and the world by providing an educational environment
of academic excellence and respect for the intrinsic value and dignity
of each person. We foster international awareness in undergraduate
and graduate programs in the liberal arts and professional studies
where talented, diverse persons of all faiths and many ages, nations
and cultures develop the intellectual, moral and professional competencies
for lifelong learning, leadership, service to others, careers, and
responsible, values-based, caring lives."
And this, from the school's Vision statement:
"Bellarmine University aspires to be the innovative,
premier independent Catholic liberal arts university in Kentucky
and the region for preparing diverse persons to become dynamic leaders
to serve, live and work in a changing, global community."
In other words, the school's entire purpose is consistent
with the search for diversity and equity, and entirely inconsistent
with the racism and Nazism of persons like Chira. So why shouldn't
the school seek to ensure that only persons who adhere to, buy into,
and are prepared to further the purpose of the institution itself,
are admitted or hired to work there? Once there, individuals may
indeed have free speech rights that protect even their most obnoxious
of views, but that says nothing about the ability of the school
to take steps that will make it much harder for such individuals
to enter the institution to begin with.
Making a proven commitment to antiracist values a
prerequisite for entry (and perhaps requiring some form of training
in these issues or antiracist service project in order to graduate
or receive tenure or promotion) would go far towards operationalizing
the college's lofty (but thusfar mostly impotent) mission, and would
make controversies such as the present one far less frequent or
relevant.
If Bellarmine is serious about stamping out racism,
it is this kind of institutional change -- which would both limit
the presence of racists and increase the numbers of people of color
and white antiracist allies, by definition -- that they should adopt.
No more platitudes, no more promises, and no more unnecessary debates
about free speech. Create an antiracist culture from the get-go,
by expanding affirmative action, diversifying the curricula, and
using admissions and hiring criteria that sends a clear signal:
namely, you may have free speech, but so do we; and we are
exercising ours to tell you that you are not welcome here.
Sadly, perhaps the most important missing ingredient
in the struggle to uproot racism, is white outrage: not at those
who challenge racism (oh we've plenty of anger for them, typically),
but rather, at those who are white like us, and whose racism we
listen to with amusement, more so than indignation.
So, for example, notice how the free speech supporters
wax eloquent about the importance of upholding Chira's right to
be a racist prick, but they evince almost no hostility towards he
and his message, beyond the obligatory throw-away line: "I
completely reject his views, but will fight for his right to express
them." In other words, they are far more worked up about the
possibility (however slight it appears to be) that the Administration
may sanction the Nazi, than they are about the fact that there
is a Nazi on their campus in the first place. Which brings up
the question: does Nazism not bother them that much? Or have they
confused the valid concept of free speech with the completely invalid
notion that one shouldn't even condemn racists, out of some misplaced
fealty to their rights (which notion of course relinquishes one's
own right to speak back, and forcefully, to assholes like
Chira)?
I long for the day when whites will get as angry at
one of our number supporting bigotry and genocidal political movements,
as we do at those who denounce the bigots and suggest that the right
of students of color to be educated in a non-hostile environment
is just as important as the right to spout putrid inanities.
What's more, I long for the day when whites stage
sit-ins to demand a more diverse and equitable college environment
for students of color (which currently is threatened by rollbacks
of affirmative action, for example), just as quickly as we stage
them to defend free speech for fascists, which, at Bellarmine at
least, shows no signs of being endangered, so quick has the Administration
been to defend Chira's liberties.
In the final analysis, when whites take it upon ourselves
to make racists and Nazis like Chira feel unwelcome at our colleges
and in our workplaces, by virtue of making clear our own views in
opposition to them, all talk of hate speech codes will become superfluous.
Where anti-racists are consistent, persistent, and uncompromising,
and where anti-racist principles are woven into the fabric of our
institutions, there will be no need to worry about people like Chira
any longer.
Racism, Free Speech and the College Campus
- Part Two:
Bigots' Personal Growth Shouldn't Come at Expense
of Others
December 29, 2005
Recently, I published an essay concerning racism on
college campuses and the issue of free speech. The commentary was
prompted by news that Andrei Chira, a freshman at Bellarmine University,
in Louisville, has been wearing a neo-Nazi armband around the school
for the better part of the Fall semester.
In the body of the piece, I sought to do three things.
First, I wanted to present the facts of the case at
Bellarmine, and describe the conflict between those who oppose any
limits to free expression, and those who feel certain types of hateful
speech may be so intimidating to students of color (as an isolated
and small minority), that certain limits might be acceptable, in
the form of restrictive hate speech codes.
Secondly, I sought to examine the free speech issue,
ultimately noting that I find neither the arguments of the free
speech absolutists, nor the hate speech code advocates entirely
persuasive.
To the free speech absolutists, I pointed out that
there are many forms of speech limits we live with, and virtually
all support (bans on harassment, libel, slander, perjury, plagiarism,
etc). Furthermore, I tried to explain that rights always must be
balanced (in this case, free speech and the First Amendment against
equal protection and the Fourteenth), so that certain types of speech,
such as one-on-one racist invective or speech that carries an implied
threat of violence can obviously be restricted without running afoul
of personal liberties we rightly wish to protect.
To those advocating speech code restrictions, I pointed
out that such efforts are cheap, easy, but ultimately not the best
way to fight racism. First, they reduce racism to interpersonal
conflict (rather than an institutional problem reinforced by power
imbalances), and encourage the belief that racism is only to be
found at the extremes: manifested by those who use racial slurs
or wear Nazi symbols, for example. Passing such restrictions allows
institutional elites to think they've done something, even when,
in truth, the most pernicious (and often more subtle) forms of racism
persist: old boy's networks that determine hiring, or unequal educational
resources that constrain higher ed access to begin with.
And finally, I sought to present an alternative to
either hate speech restrictions or merely doing nothing. Specifically,
I noted that if Chira has free speech, and has the right to offend
and make persons of color uncomfortable, then so too do others.
As such, Bellarmine students should exercise their free speech,
by wearing anti-racist, anti-Nazi, or even anti-Andrei Chira armbands.
Likewise, they should refuse to speak to him or associate with him
in any way (after all, free speech also means the freedom not
to speak). Lastly, Bellarmine should operationalize their mission
and vision statements (both of which stress the importance of cultural
diversity and human dignity in a global environment), by requiring
persons seeking to attend school or work there to demonstrate a
commitment to racial equity and justice in order to enter the institution,
or once there, to graduate, be promoted, or receive tenure.
To these suggestions, and the larger argument, I received
many responses, most of which were favorable, but some of which
seemed to have missed my point altogether. Several apparently thought
I had called for speech restrictions, and proceeded to lecture me
about the slippery slope that might follow such mandates. Since
most of my readers are fairly liberal or left to begin with, these
typically sounded the alarm that communists or anarchists might
be next - prohibited from expressing their views because they would
offend others.
Of course, in point of fact, I had not endorsed speech
codes or restrictions on hate speech (except in the fairly obvious
cases of one-on-one harassment or invective, which no rational person
would want to defend, and speech that includes a threat of violence).
I did not take a position as to what should happen with Andre Chira,
in terms of his right to wear the armband, and generally, to be
a racist ass. If anything, my endorsement of alternatives to speech
codes at the end of the piece suggests I am not a fan of speech
restrictions, even if I reject the absolutists' claims about slippery
slopes as horribly simplistic.
Among the litany of responses I received, however,
one stood out for its depth of thought, its well argued counterpoint
to my own position, and the desire on the part of the author to
engage the issues from the perspective of how best to address racism,
which, after all, is the primary concern here. As such, and despite
disagreeing with her position, I felt it would be useful to give
voice to her criticisms, and then explain why I feel that my suggestions
in the original piece remain valid.
The person who took issue with my original article,
made several arguments, which roughly can be synthesized to the
following:
- Andrei Chira is young, clueless and insecure, and
like many such persons, looking for scapegoats and an identity
for his own unexamined rage;
- Although this hardly excuses his actions, it suggests
he is in need of education, not ostracism, as I recommended, or
the donning of armbands directed at him personally, or hostility
more generally. After all, to further marginalize him (in his
own mind at least) and to shame him for his views, might only
generate more of the hostility and rage that animated his original
gravitation to neo-Nazism, and thereby make his racism worse;
and finally,
- For Bellarmine (or other schools) to restrict access
to people like Chira in the first place (by making a commitment
to equity and diversity a qualification for admission) would only
prevent racists from being exposed to alternative ways of thinking,
thereby allowing them to remain ignorant, and thus, more dangerous
to the society at large.
Because the person penning this response was making
a heartfelt (and I would say quite reasonable) argument about what
is, and is not, the best way to fight racism, it is important to
engage her concerns. After all, if my suggestions would, on balance,
make things worse, then obviously as a committed antiracist activist,
I would want to rethink them. But having thought about the concerns
expressed above, I feel there are a multitude of problems with the
"educate don't ostracize" position being put forth by
the person in question.
Patience and Education at Whose Expense?
To begin with, even as we acknowledge that persons
like Chira suffer from a profound ignorance, and that it is important
for such persons to have that ignorance challenged with wisdom,
this truism yet begs the question: At whose expense should Chira's
education come?
So, for example, should Chira's need for a guiding
and patient hand to help him work through his rage, stupidity or
whatever, be thought of as more important than - or even equally
as important as - the right of students, staff and faculty of color
to be able to work and go to school in environments free from overt
forms of racist hostility? In other words, even to the extent we
agree that it would be best - all things equal - for us to re-educate
Chira and not ostracize him or shame him, to what extent should
persons of color be expected to bear the weight of this re-education
process?
I have long agreed that it is important for those
of us who are white to be patient and even forgiving towards other
whites (and ourselves) for falling into racist patterns of thought:
after all, everything in our culture encourages exactly that direction.
But there is a difference between exhibiting that patience and forgiveness,
when the only person from whom it requires sacrifice is oneself,
and, on the other hand, demanding that same patience and forgiveness
from others - in this case, the targets of Chira's racism. Asking
folks of color at Bellarmine to suffer fools (whether gladly or
not), and to put their own feelings of insecurity and even danger
on the back burner while we caring white folks try to fix one of
our lost flock - one who attends classes with them, after all, and
who lives in their dorms - well, that seems like a bit much to me.
This is made all the more true by the possibility
- and even likelihood - that if folks like Chira are allowed to
spout racism and avoid ostracism when they do so, out of
concern for not shaming him into being an even bigger jackass, people
of color at schools like Bellarmine may leave the institution, unsure
that whites there are really concerned about their safety or fears
about racism. Alternately, other folks of color may refuse to apply,
enroll or attend at all. Thus, our heartfelt efforts to educate
Chira and not drive him out (or others like him), would likely result
in an even smaller number and percentage of people of color attending
mostly white schools, thereby sacrificing their educational
access and opportunities for the sake of his. That such a
result would be exactly the goal of white supremacists - less black
and brown folks around - shouldn't be lost on us here, and the irony
of obtaining an institutionally racist result, even as we try and
cure one individual of his own personal racism, should give anyone
pause who thinks that this would be the best direction in which
we should move.
Saving Individual Racists or Reducing Institutional
Racism?
As for the suggestion that adopting an antiracist
criteria for admission to the University, or for obtaining a job
there would result in merely "preaching to the choir,"
while leaving racists to their own devices, unlikely to be exposed
to the healing balm of higher learning (a legitimate concern expressed
by the individual who wrote to me), there are a few shortcomings
with regard to this argument.
First, such a criteria or screening process (or requirement
that graduating or receiving tenure requires antiracist training
or some form of service project) would, almost by definition, boost
the numbers and percentages of folks of color on the campus. After
all, such persons are likely to have firm commitments to diversity
and equity, and to have given serious thought as to how to move
such goals forward. In other words, by definition, such a criteria
would result in a diminution of white campus hegemony, and thus,
again, by definition, result in a reduction in institutional racism
and white supremacy.
What this suggests, is that even if screening out
racists removed one more opportunity to educate them, as individuals,
away from racism (a fair and essentially true proposition), such
screening would at the same time guarantee a reduction in institutional
racism, which surely must rank as a more impactful problem, in both
quantitative and qualitative terms. So that even if one accepts
as true the concern expressed above, one could still rightly conclude
that it is more important to reduce institutional inequity and racism
at a given college, than to ensure that one individual person is
able to matriculate there, and perhaps become a better person in
the process.
Additionally, such a screening process or antiracist
requirement would increase the numbers of antiracist white allies
on the campus, as opposed to either racist whites or those who've
never given the subject much thought or concern. This, in turn,
would produce something of an incubator for developing antiracist
strategies, in this case in Louisville, but potentially elsewhere
too. Such an environment would allow for the development of a stronger
cadre of antiracists, and as such, might be seen as more than balancing
out whatever lost opportunities obtain vis-a-vis people like Chira.
The question is whether it is more important to "save"
Chira, or to develop a setting in which antiracist whites (or those
willing to become antiracists) can grow, learn and become better
allies to people of color?
The Difference Between Hate Speech and Mere Ignorance
While it is absolutely vital to provide the antiracist
counterweight and balance to whatever racism people like Chira are
ingesting, the question of where and when such weight needs to be
provided - and at what point it's simply too late to prioritize
this goal, however otherwise valid it may be - remains on the table.
So while we must surely push for this kind of antiracist "character"
education to be part of the K-12 curriculum, hoping to deal with
such overt racism once a student has become an adult and entered
college is considerably more problematic.
Perhaps if the racism in question were of the standard,
garden-variety type (or even of the relatively highbrow pseudo-scientific
brand, which can nonetheless be answered by better science), providing
that counterweight might not be too much of a burden or threat to
people of color. But when we're talking about racism of the vicious,
Hitler-worshipping type, in which there is no cogent argument being
made, beyond "whites are the master race," blacks are
"mud-people," and Jews should be exterminated, it's hard
to believe that a college either can, or should be expected, to
turn one back from the precipice of their own hateful psychological
abyss.
At the very least, if we conclude that free speech
requires the school and its community members to indulge such sickness,
we certainly should not also take away (or criticize) their power
to shame the hater, ridicule him, or make him feel like the unacceptable
outcast he is. Again, the question is not about Chira's rights alone,
but also the rights of others at the school to exercise their free
speech to isolate him, and make clear their own revulsion at his
views, until he either stops acting out, or leaves.
It is worth noting here that Chira's particular form
of racist speech - the brandishing of a neo-Nazi symbol - or certain
other forms, like the use of overt racial slurs, are all quite different
from some of the milder, albeit offensive kinds of racist discourse
that typically takes place on campuses, and which can best be addressed
by way of re-education efforts.
So, for example, every year it seems as though at
least one (and usually several) colleges have a "blackface
incident," in which ignorant white kids smear greasepaint on
their faces so as to appear black. Each time, the perpetrators find
this stunt - the viciously racist history of which they know nothing
at all (because of course we don't teach about those kinds of things
in school) - to be hilarious, even an example of bonding with their
several "black friends." (Seriously, this was said by
several young women at Stetson University, in Deland, Florida this
fall, when they dressed up like black basketball players).
As infuriating as such displays of stupidity are,
it can be fairly said that in almost every case, those engaged in
the act are truly, purely ignorant; this, as opposed to persons
who identify openly with Hitlerism. Even if one doesn't fully understand
the vagaries of National Socialism - what it means, what it meant,
and what was done in its name - it is simply not conceivable that
anyone who had reached the age of eighteen would not be aware of
the basic core of ideas being endorsed by embracing its symbols.
And surely one would have to know how flaunting such a symbol would
make someone feel who was a person of color, or Jewish, for example.
So while it is likely that an otherwise non-bigoted
person whose ignorance led them to don blackface or commit some
similarly asinine act of micro-level racism, could be changed for
the better by educational efforts aimed at filling in the gaps in
their knowledge, the neo-Nazi is not merely ignorant. Chira may
say that his identification with National Socialism is merely because
of his support for national health care and a good forestry program
(yes, he does say this), but if we believe him, we are considerably
more stupid than he is. To the extent he says such a thing he is
not merely a racist, but also a liar - both of which things rise
to the level of character flaws serious enough to justify his being
ostracized and vilified by any and everyone on the Bellarmine campus.
The Value of Scorn and Rebuke
It's also worth noting that, on occasion, being stigmatized
really does work to change behavior, if not one's core feelings
and beliefs. Most people, for good or bad, tend to conform to strongly
held and communicated social norms, and even bend their behavior
to fit these norms. While we may lament conformity in many cases
- indeed, in many areas of life we desperately need people to be
more questioning of socially accepted "norms" of behavior
- in the sense that most people conform to reining in overt manifestations
of racist bigotry (something they wouldn't have done even forty
years ago), conformity can only be seen as a blessing. If institutions
send a clear message that bigots will be seen and treated as rejects
- friendless, and undeserving of understanding or compassion until
they cease engaging in the behavior that is so injurious to others
- many persons so ostracized would indeed change their ways. Granted,
they might remain racist internally, but they will be inclined to
keep things to themselves, which, after all, is really the primary
thing the victims of racism care about.
Which raises the next question: namely, is a person
who so cavalierly dismisses the feelings of others - such that they
would outwardly identify with a movement that endorses the oppression
and even extermination of entire groups of people - already such
an anti-social personality that they are beyond the point of being
transformed solely by exposure to an especially good sociology professor?
Or at least, might they be so abnormally wired so as to make such
a conversion experience exceedingly difficult, and surely more of
a project than any college can be expected to undertake on its own?
If Chira is not an antisocial personality,
he will care what others think and may indeed be inclined to change
when challenged and made to understand that his views make him a
pariah. If he is an antisocial personality, such that he
doesn't care what others think (or even enjoys upsetting people
in this way) then he is not likely to change or grow in response
to patiently dispensed education, any more than the schoolyard bully
is likely to alter behavior because someone sits him down and tells
him that there are better ways to deal with anger than by fighting.
Conclusion: The Importance of Choosing Sides
At the end of the day, schools have a right, and more,
an obligation to define their missions and operationalize those
missions in the policies, practices and procedures they employ.
In fact, a failure to define one's mission clearly, and then hew
policies to that mission invites the devolution of higher ed to
little more than a business, whose mission becomes getting higher
and higher marks in the U.S. News college rankings, and thereby
bringing in more alumni contributions, government research contracts,
and elite students. Too often schools develop lofty missions but
then do nothing to make those missions real in practice: so they
preach diversity, equity, and even social justice, but ignore those
concepts in their day-to-day operations. As such, they end up with
people like Andrei Chira, on occasion: people who have never seen
the mission, been asked about it, or been forced to explain - as
a condition of their acceptance - how they would further it, or
if they even cared about it at all.
And yes, this means that schools would have the right
to define their missions as the training of the next generation
of capitalists, or to evangelize the world with their own brands
of Christianity, and to keep out those who didn't agree with those
missions, but so what? At least they would have to be open about
those values, in which case those of us not wishing to be investment
bankers or body snatched and drafted into Jesus' army would be able
to steer clear of such places.
Ultimately, the biggest problem with the "educate
him, don't ostracize him" approach is that it prioritizes Chira's
needs and interests over those of others: others who have done nothing
wrong, quite unlike Chira. Blacks, Latinos, Asians, Jews, and queer
students are also at the University for their personal and
intellectual growth, every bit as much as Chira. They attend college
so they can be nurtured, learn new things, and have old ways of
thinking challenged on any number of subjects, as with Chira. To
defer to Andrei Chira's need for growth and exposure to truth, and
to prioritize that need, even at the expense of running off
folks of color, Jews and gay and lesbian folks from the campus,
is to suggest that he is more entitled to a Bellarmine education
than they are. Surely this is neither the message we hope to send,
nor the choice we wish to make, when it comes time, as it so often
does, to choose sides.
Keep track of Tim Wise's lecture schedule and
new commentaries, at www.timwise.org
. Check out Tim's books, White Like Me: Reflections
on Race from a Privileged Son, and Affirmative Action:
Racial Preference in Black and White at a bookstore near you,
or online at Amazon.com. |