The Negro’s experience of the
white world cannot
possibly create in him any respect
for the standards
which the white world claims to live
James Baldwin,
The Fire Next Time: My Dungeon Shook; Down at the Cross
Committed to freedom and equality,
Karl Marx recognized that democracy was the only solution for
achieving a constitution for “real human beings” and for
“real people” to posit a “people’s own
creation,” writes Swedish philosopher Martin Hägglund. As
an institution, democracy makes possible the rise of “the
profound secular recognition that we are
responsible for organizing and legislating the form of our life
together.”
This Life: Secular Faith and Spiritual Freedom, Hägglund calls on Marx’s critique of capitalism in order
to explain why it is that “we cannot invoke religious dogma as
the final word in a debate or as the founding authority of law.”
For Marx, writes Hägglund, “the law exists for the sake of
human beings,” rather than to appease a supernatural entity. On
the other hand, while Marx recognizes the right of everyone to have a
vote, as “a necessary condition
for a truly free society,” he also understood that the
achieving of civil rights was not the end of the people’s
struggle. Our economy must be front and center in our deliberations
about the democracy we want to see come about. “This is why
capitalism and actual democracy are incompatible,” writes
Hägglund.
It’s
the economy that features a measure of value that is
“self-contradictory.” In capitalism, Marx understood that
what matters is growth—not of humanity but rather of capital
itself. The thing and
all the things capitalism
begets, matters. What is value if not wealth? “If our social
wealth depends on the growth of capital, we have no choice but to
promote the purpose of profit, since our wealth as society depends on
it.”
Human
beings are of no worth—not so valuable if poor or homeless or
unemployed or someone working two jobs to pay the rent. Thus the
pursuit of secular faith or spiritual freedom would seem a luxury
rather than a way we could exists as human beings. How is it possible
to create new occupations when those occupations are not valued in a
society that insists instead that we create occupations “that
are profitable on the market, since only such occupations generate a
growth of value in the economy”? As Hägglund writes, we
need a “revaluation of value” if democratic socialism is
ever to “overcome” capitalism. Socialism shouldn’t
become “a matter of distributing the wealth generated by
proletarian labor in a more equal way across society.”
I
think back to how so many Americans welcomed the election of the
first black president in Barack Obama. However different racial,
Obama engaged nonetheless in the same practice of imperialist and
capitalist war and conflict for control of the cultural and political
narrative and material resources in which to extract more wealth from
the many for the few. The black president deported more migrant
workers than did President Bush, Jr. Americans of color endure the
continuation of discrimination and police brutality. The economic
system, however, was left unchanged, in fact, we can even recall
witnessing the practice of socialism for the banks and other
too-big-to-fail corporations. The dictates of the capitalist market
performed well, for it was business as usual for the black president
too.
“Coerced
proletarian labor,” as Marx noted, is no better than coerced
wage labor. The transformation must be politically democratic and
economically socialist. In a transformation of the economic system,
there’s a focus on freedom. Not Hollywood’s version of
freedom, however, where all the clothing comes off and the hair is
short on one side and long on the other. The struggle
isn’t about superficial change that still is valued on the
“free” market.
On
the contrary, for Marx, Hägglund writes, “to be free is
not to be free from normative constraints, but to be free to
negotiate, transform, and
challenge the constraints of the practical identities in light of
which we lead our lives.” The question we must ask ourselves,
Hägglund continues, is “not if our
freedom will be formed by social institutions—there can be no
freedom that does not have an institutional form—but how
and by which social
institutions our freedom will be formed.” Institutions, then,
writes Hägglund, would enable individuals to lead their lives in
light of the recognition that their “dependence on others would
result in collective projects” that have value for human
beings.
We’d
recognize ourselves and our freedom in these institutions, which in
turn, wouldn’t require our coercion but rather our commitment
to participate in what benefits everyone. Keep in mind that the aim
of proletarian labor isn’t to “glorify” it, but
instead “to overcome it.” Marx’s motto - “from
each according to his ability, to each according to his needs”-
is the condition for the “possibility for genuinely democratic
deliberations regarding what matters to us and how we should care for
one another,” Hägglund adds.
Democratic
emancipation, Hägglund continues, requires the end of religious
promises of eternal life as well as the end of the free market
promising wealth and equality for all but impoverishing more and more
of humanity while destroying our material resources. Hägglund
cites Marx’s observation that the call to abandon the illusion
“about their conditions,” that is capitalism and
religion, is, quoting Marx, a “‘call to abandon
a condition which requires illusions.’”
In contrast to democratic socialism,
capitalism, Hägglund writes,
“we are all in practice committed to a purpose in which we
cannot recognize ourselves, which, inevitably leads to alienated
forms of social life.” As a result of this social ordering of
life, our needs and abilities are secondary to the necessity for us,
society, to produce wealth. The capitalist measure of value
contradicts and betrays while promising emancipation. It’s
emancipation for a few who, in turn, suffer no shame in reminded
their flock of poor and middle class workers about eternity—the
reward for working hard yet earning less than livable wages.
In
contrast to life under the brutal economic system of capitalism, the
first principle of democratic socialism would be to measure our
wealth in terms of “socially available free time,”
Hägglund explains.
What
a life that would be?
When
I thought about Dr. Martin L. King, Jr., I conjured up an image of
Uncle Tom. I’m a teen and anyone over 30-years old was old in
1968. Anyone preaching non-violence was certainly an Uncle Tom. I
loved Malcolm and missed him by 1968, a few months after King was
assassinated. By 1969, when I joined the Southern Christian
Leadership Conference (SCLC) in Chicago, and the young Jesse Jackson
was our leader, I hadn’t changed my mind about King. He was an
Uncle Tom until I stopped in-taking white America’s narratives
about itself, contaminated as they still are with doses and doses of
toxic innocence.
For
Hägglund, too, across the ocean in Sweden, the “middle-class
preacher” in pursuit of “middle-class goals” was
King. This representation of
King, far from radical, is deliberately intended to conceal the
radical activist, hated by both the political and religious
establishments, particularly after his 1967 Riverside Speech, in
which he comes out against the war in Vietnam. King wasn’t
preaching about that pie-in-the-sky, by-and-by, but, rather, how our
home Earth demanded our attention. Humanity on Earth, life on Earth,
perpetually demands our attention, for we should be humble guardians
not money-hungry tyrants.
For
King, it wasn’t a matter of reforming the state of unfreedom
and inequality. As Hägglund notes, the first phase of the
struggle, begun in 1955 with the Montgomery boycott, was an all-out
blitz against unjust laws, resulting (ten years later) in the
overturning of Jim Crow legislation and the passage of the Voting
Rights Act. There was nothing subtle about the torture and murder of
activists or the bombing of churches and homes. Certainly the anger
and hatred whites feeling defeated again lead to the second phase,
where King exercising far more “radical measures,” isn’t
courting the “goodwill” of government, but instead
develops tactics to “compel unwilling authorities to yield to
the mandates of justice.”
King’s
Poor People’s Campaign is one result of this second phase
strategy; it’s goal, far from benefiting the middle class, was
intended to be a “‘genuine class movement’
transcending racial and ethnic lines to include Native Americans and
Hispanics,” poor and working class whites as well as the
unemployed. In Memphis, hours before he is murdered, King told the
press: “‘You could say we are engaged in a class
struggle, yes.’” Why—because “‘something
is wrong with capitalism.’” He labored with trying to
change the system from within for years, but now, it was a new day!
“‘I
feel quite differently, I think you’ve got to have a
reconstruction of the entire society, a revaluation of values.’”
“A
revaluation of values”!
This
isn’t the King the media described before or after his death.
As a teen in the North, raised in a Catholic family who believed
Baptist to be heathens, for openers, King was a troublemaker.
In my family, it was who is Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr.?
In
subsequent years, I’ve read King’s speeches and his
writings. From my research, arose a phoenix. Sounds like the man read
Karl Marx. I’d venture to say I suspect that over time he was
less and less religious and more a human being in pursuit of freedom.
When I read that This Life concluded
with a discussion on King’s pursuit of freedom and equality, I
wasn’t surprised.
Neither
Marx nor King could begin to analyze the pursuit of freedom and
equality without discussing the wrongs of an economic system that
represents the direct opposition of democracy (freedom and equality).
However, both thinkers considered ways to disable cruel and unjust
policies. Both Marx and King prioritized freedom on Earth rather than
eternity in the elsewhere. For both thinkers, capitalism was not a
given.
For
King in particular, “‘the problem of racism, the problem
of economic exploitation, and the problem of war’” are
all of a piece. Yet, Hägglund explains, King’s “radical
legacy” is ignored in cultural celebrations of his birthday and
death. It’s ignored in the way textbooks frame his activism and
work as examples of a Southern preacher, advocating non-violence. In
other words, King became an advocate for the good behavior
of African Americans. Hägglund, quotes the late Rev. Hosea
Williams, fellow activist with King: “‘there is a
definite effort on the part of Americans to change Martin Luther
King, Jr. from what he was all about—to make him the Uncle Tom
of the century. In my mind, he was the militant of the century.’”
As
Hägglund rightly points out, King called for a “redistribution
of wealth.” King recognized that the root problem stifling
freedom, equality, and justice is “fundamental economics.”
Hägglund, citing a speech King gave at the Workers Union of
America in 1962, recognizes the activist in King shifting from a
liberal stands to a radical one, calling for the complete dissolving
of an unjust economic system. King: “‘We cannot create
machines which revolutionize industry unless we simultaneously create
ideas commensurate with social and economic re-organization, which
harness the power of such machines for the benefit of man. The new
age will not be an era of hope but of fear and emptiness unless we
master this problem.’” All those decades before, King
recognized that life in a thing-oriented society produces slaves of
hate rather than human beings in pursuit of freedom.
King
transformed; he becomes an individual for whom the economic system
can no longer appease with the latest technology or fashion. There is
something at stake, something worth dying for. After all, freedom is
to love while engaged in the battle to overcoming hate.
In
Marx’s version of King’s “I Have a Dream,” he
speaks of transforming “our understanding of our struggle, our
dreams, and our desires,” thus overcoming the contradictions
within the practice of religion and politics.” Isn’t this
understanding of our reality the lesson that the philosopher King
learns about the struggle?
In
the long run, Hägglund argues, the struggle, difficult as it is,
must be sustained. He considers his own work, his own “philosophical
account” as a thinker and writer to be “a part of the
revolution, rather than external to it.” “The lives we
lead,” Hägglund adds, “the form of society we
sustain, will always depend on us and on what we do with our time.”
|