Note:
This commentary is a response by Bill Fletcher, Jr. to a forum
published by Boston Review in which the authors James Gray Pope, Ed
Bruno and Peter Kellman postulate: "Unions are being strangled
by laws that block workers from organizing, striking, and acting in
solidarity. Becoming a rights-based movement is the only way to save
labor."
Pope,
Bruno, and Kellman lay out the case for how organized labor is being
strangled by existing labor laws and employer repression. One of
their principle concerns is to reform the system of exclusive
representation that shapes unions in the United States. Exclusive
representation was introduced into the National Labor Relations Act
in response to fear by legislators of industrial chaos or civil war.
Such chaos was believed to be possible if there were multiple unions
competing with one another and attempting to bargain with an
employer. The authors offer a useful critique of exclusive
representation and question whether a different system should be
introduced. At the same time, they do not address what I believe to
be the preeminent concern, particularly in times such as these: the
possibility of the introduction of company “unions” in
the absence of exclusive representation.
Abandoning
exclusive representation creates conditions in which there could be
not only competition from other unions, but also attempts by
employers to create organizations positioned as allegedly
representing workers, but which in fact prioritize the interests of
the employer class. This could significantly undercut legitimate
workers’ organizations, most of which could never match the
resources that employers could shower upon their own sanctioned
organizations.
For
this reason, Pope, Bruno, and Kellman should incorporate a very
strong stand against any
employer involvement—including but not limited to
interference—in workers’ choices of whether, when, and
how they should be represented. In fact, the matter of employer
involvement must become a sharper element in today’s fight for
workers’ rights. The threat of national right-to-work laws has
made this need more urgent than ever.
The
employer class should not have any
involvement in the decision by workers to join or form their own
organization. This includes employers expressing preferences about
how their workers should organize. To claim this as a matter of free
speech is a canard because of the profound and fundamental power
imbalance between workers and employers. Because of this imbalance,
employers’ expressions of preference inherently contain an
element of coercion. The employer has the advantage of being able to
carry out policies that penalize workers for their choices. The
employer can close down, reorganize, and terminate workers—or,
should exclusive representation be eliminated, establish sanctioned
“employee associations” that are actually instruments of
the company.
Employers’
ability to involve themselves in their workers’ right to choose
how they organize undermines the possibility of real democracy. This
is for the same reason that in elections, it is so important that
there be no intimidations at the polls to guarantee that voters
choose freely and fairly. In a worker’s choice for
representation, however, while said rules should apply, in reality
they do not. Employers are able to carry out various forms of
intimidation with either no or limited ramifications. The penalties
for most violations of the National Labor Relations Act are so
minimal that it is actually in the interests of employers to break
the law to chill efforts at worker organization.
For
these reasons, altering labor laws without denying employers the
right to involve themselves in a worker’s choice of whether,
when, and how to be represented will not address the fundamental
power imbalance in the workplace and might even worsen it.
At
bottom is the authoritarian nature of the U.S. workplace. This is a
point that Barbara Ehrenreich has emphasized for years. The average
worker enters the workplace and, in the absence of a union or
collective bargaining, finds herself in a dictatorial environment,
losing her basic rights, including the rights to freedom of
association, freedom of speech, and freedom of the press. She exists
in an environment where she is presumed guilty rather than innocent
in the face of any infractions because, in the absence of collective
bargaining or a legally enforceable personalized contract, most
workplaces have no just cause provisions.
In
the early 2000s Ehrenreich began asking why this fact is not central
to the mission and message of organized labor. Why do unions almost
never explicitly address the authoritarian nature of the workplace?
In other words, why is organized labor not a rights-based movement?
Underlying this crisis is a failure to engage the notion of union
transformation,
and specifically, the need for what Fernando Gapasin and I have
termed “social justice unionism.”
This
shortcoming is not only the result of the Taft-Hartley–amended
NLRA, which greatly restricted the powers of unions, but also that
organized labor has long accepted the framework established by
American Federation of Labor’s first president, Samuel Gompers,
a framework even further contracted by the Cold War. Gompers
envisioned trade unions as instruments for securing wages, better
hours, and safer working conditions, not as instruments for overall
social and economic justice. The Cold War repressed and altered the
trade union movement, narrowing its vision. Major unions, including
the United Auto Workers, came to accept the notion that collective
bargaining should be the principal means for addressing the broad
concerns of workers, such as health care. Rather than standing firm
for societal entitlements and the expansion of democracy, organized
labor slowly but noticeably turned its attention inward in order to
focus upon those who were already represented by unions. During this
time efforts by left-led unions to expand the parameters of trade
unionism were crushed and treated as antithetical to the goals of
allegedly legitimate trade unionism.
As
a result organized labor retreated from a social vision. In part
because of this, it was increasingly unable to address changes in the
workforce and methods of work, as well as the evolution of global
capitalism. Instead of leading a broad social movement for progress,
trade unionism turned away and focused on industrial jurisprudence.
Organized labor, in most cases and with certain notable exceptions,
rather than being perceived as an instrument for broader
justice—including but not limited to racial and gender
justice—was viewed as either irrelevant or an obstacle.
Even
should labor laws change for the better, if organized labor does not
first shift its paradigm, it will fail to seize upon the new
possibilities. An warning sign of this can be found in the attraction
that some labor leaders have for Donald Trump because of their belief
that he will bring about new (or old) employment. Despite the fact
that Trump ran a racist, sexist, xenophobic campaign, some trade
union leaders feel this is either irrelevant or that it can be
ignored in the name of increasing employment. Such a vision sets
unions against the interests of huge sections of the working class.
It also puts organized labor at odds with other social movements,
including the environmental movement. This means condemning organized
labor to being not a social movement but, to borrow from Ronald
Reagan, a special
interest
or a minority constituency.
Pope,
Bruno, and Kellman correctly challenge the restrictions inherent in
the Taft-Hartley–amended National Labor Relations Act. They are
on point in demonstrating that the existing labor laws place
significant, if not undemocratic, restrictions on the possibility for
workers to exercise their right to freedom of association and
collective bargaining. That said, in the absence of a shift in the
vision of trade unionism, statutory changes are insufficient to
address the impact of neoliberal globalization on the working class.
|